The distinction of insanity Essay

Free Human Computer Interaction Individual Report Essay Sample



FOR YOU for only $24.38 $20.00/page

Custom Student Mr.Teacher ENG1001-04 January 6, 2018

The distinction of insanity

The distinction between insanity, automatism and diminished responsibility in the Laws of England and Wales. Covers the Management rule which is also a dominant rule in US legal doctrine. By “The defendant who seeks to avoid criminal allowably on the basis that s/he was suffering from a mental disorder at the time of the alleged crime must have a defense that falls within one of the following, legally recognized, categories: Insanity, Diminished Responsibility or Automatism. While, at one level or another, these “mental disorder defenses” share common characteristics, they each differ significantly. Fortunately, this point does not appear to be fully appreciated in English Law. ” Discuss the validity of this statement. Inherent in our legal system is an idea of culpability. The word itself embodies notions of moral responsibility and blame. There are two elements that will allow us to determine whether or not someone is to be considered culpable. The first is that the person on whom we wish to apportion blame Is an actual agent of harm as opposed to a mere causer. That Is to say that they are Instrumental In an action and are not simply a victim of a spasm or similar associated condition.

The second is that e/she has the capacity to understand the laws and moral order that exist within society. Hart’s principles of Justice assert that ‘a moral license to punish is needed by society and unless a man has the capacity and fair opportunity or chance to adjust his behavior to the law, its penalties ought not be applied to him. ” Such deep- rooted notions of culpability have necessitated development In the area of defenses to ensure that those who fall outside of the legally recognized parameters of accountability are afforded protection’. Amongst such defenses are Insanity, Automatism and Diminished responsibility.

This essay will identify the similarities and differences of these defenses by exploring their theoretical foundations and determine whether, in practice, they are sufficiently understood by the courts to achieve their desired end. The theoretical basis for an Insanity defense Is embedded In the notions of fair opportunity as discussed above. It is felt that the insane man is too far removed from normality to make us angry with him’. The impetus of the law and its functions might well be considered outside of his comprehension and similarly, so too might the moral implications of his act.

Therefore, it would not be either ‘efficacious or equitable’ to hold such a man criminally responsible . As Duff remarks of the why it is being done, or how it is related as a punishment to her past offence, her punishment becomes a travesty? “. Therefore, if a defense of insanity is successful the defendant will be given a ‘special verdict’ namely ‘not guilty by reason of insanity’. Although this special verdict may bring indefinite detention (a fact which is reconciled in theory by ‘compelling considerations of public interest’ ) it still serves to reflect a lack of culpability and therefore, blame.

The basis on which the non-insane automatism defense is founded is somewhat more fundamental than that of insanity. It was developed to exculpate those who had been the victim of events rather than those who had fallen foul to circumstance . A plea of automatism is ‘not merely a denial of fault, or of responsibility. It is more a denial of authorship’ in the sense that the automaton is in no way instrumental in any criminal act. Lord Deadline remarked in Alphabet that “an inadvertent and unintended act without negligence? Might be said, not caused’. Others have described such acts as ‘acts of god’.

It is with this class of act that the defense of automatism is concerned – acts which might be said seen as ‘inconsistent with the requirement of an cactus reuse’ . This lack-of-instrumentality concept is reflected by the fact that on a finding of automatism a defendant will be granted an unqualified acquittal by the courts. Detention is unnecessary for as well being blameless, the automaton presents no future threat to society. Whilst Insanity and Automatism serve as general defenses in law, Diminished responsibility operates only as a defense to murder.

It offers those ‘bordering on insanity’ the opportunity to argue that at the time of the killing they were ‘suffering from such abnormality of mind’ so as to ‘substantially impair their mental responsibility’. If such an argument is successful (all other things being equal) the potential murderer will be convicted of manslaughter and hence will escape the mandatory life sentence that a finding of murder brings. The deference’s existence is justified (much like insanity) by notions of responsibility and blame.

The doctrine, it was felt, ‘was needed to reflect the view that where there was less responsibility there ought to be less punishment. Despite some clear differences in the three defenses’ theoretical foundations and intentions, it could be said that technically they have become somewhat confused in law. Discussion will now turn to the two automatism defenses before then going on to examine diminished responsibility in context. Whilst both automatism defenses are grounded in the idea that ‘where there is no responsibility there should be no blame,’ policy reasons have necessitated their independent development.

Because of this, the person who seeks to raise automatism as a defense is subject to a very tight definitional distinction. This tight definitional distinction between automatism and insanity is highlighted by Galilee Williams when he describes non-insane automatism as ‘any abnormal state of consciousness…. While not amounting to insanity. ‘ Such statements offer little and this, as will become clear, is no easy task. The contemporary framework of the insanity defense can be found in Management’s Case where Lord Tindal authoritatively ruled that? : “? O establish a defense on the ground of insanity, it must be clearly proved that, at the time of the committing of the act, the party accused was labouringly under such a effect of reason, from disease of the mind, as not to know the nature and quality of the act he was doing; or, if he did know it, that he did not know he was doing what was wrong. ” Subsequent development of a non-insane automatism defense, for reasons discussed above, necessitated Judicious refinement of these insanity parameters to insure that those who sought to invoke the former were deserving .

Therefore, considerable onus was placed upon the meaning of the rules, especially the phrase ‘disease of the mind’. First, it was decided that ‘mind’ referred to the mental faculties of reason, memory ND understanding and not simply the organic mass that is the brain. Then, in Sullivan, (the defendant was charged with assault which, he claimed, was the result of the post-octal stage of an epileptic seizure) the definition expanded to catch transient and intermittent impairment of the mind.

It was held that the permanence of a disease ‘cannot on any rational ground be relevant to the application by the courts of the Management rules’. This finding ran contrary to contemporary medical definitions and began to impinge upon the design of the non-insane automatism defense: that being to catch one-off, faultless incidents of automatism. Perhaps more significantly, Sullivan continued to develop Quick on what is now thought to be the defining boundary between the two defenses, that of internal and external causes.

This distinction was cemented in Burgess where Lord Lane explicitly referred to the difference between internal and external causes as the point on which the ‘case depends, as others have depended in the past’ The defendant in Burgess was a sleepwalker who assaulted a friend whilst in a somnambulist’s state. It was held that somnambulism was a disease of the mind under the Management rules argyle because it was considered a ‘pathological’ (and therefore, internal) condition by expert witnesses in cross-examination.

While, to some, this internal/external distinction ‘makes good sense,’ to others its effect is wholly inappropriate, as it fudges the boundaries between the theoretical rationales of insane and non-insane automatism. Irene McKay, for example (as well as pointing to contradictory obiter ) attacks the distinction with reference to its effect. She contends that sleep ‘can hardly be called an illness, disorder or abnormal condition. It is a perfectly normal condition. ‘ Of interest here, Graham Virgo points to anecdotal evidence that cheese might cause sleepwalking.

If such evidence could be of the fact that eating cheese would be considered an external cause. Such a consideration is far from easily reconcilable with the aforementioned notions of blame and responsibility as expounded by Hart’s principles of Justice. McKay continues to attack Burgess on a second defining point. She contends that the court failed to properly adopt the definition of ‘disease of the mind’ as put forward by Lord Denying in Bratty – namely that it is “any mental disorder which has manifested itself in violence and is prone to recur.

Considering statistical evidence showing that no one had ever appeared before a court twice charged with somnambulist’s violence, McKay remarks ‘something which is prone to recur must be at least ‘inclined to recur or have a tendency to recur or be to some extent likely to recur. ‘ Despite such protestations, current medical opinion is that sleepwalking is caused by internal factors and may be likely to recur . Therefore it is suitable for Management insanity as defined.

The result of these calculated distinctions between the two defenses is that ‘epileptics, sleepwalkers, those suffering from arteriosclerosis and diabetics during a hyperglycemia episode, may all now be regarded as insane. ‘ This is surely an unacceptable position. After all, such people appear to fit far more comfortably within the (theoretical) realms of automatism than insanity. They are rational people, capable of recognizing rule following situations, who are (largely) the victims of one off incidents of involuntariness.

If we are to label a diabetic insane because they neglected to take their medication, are we to do the same with one who gets a migraine from omitting to take aspirin? The difference of cause is the resultant harm and the need for the courts to protect society. Incidentally, close scrutiny of the Management rules leads us to conclude that where a defendant’s inability to recognize he was doing something wrong was due to something other than a defect of reason caused by a disease of the mind he would generally have no defense at all. Things do not get any clearer when the defense of Diminished Responsibility is brought into the frame.

The statutory provision for the defense is found in Section 2(1) of the Homicide Act 1957 and provides that a person shall not be convicted of murder: “If he was suffering from such abnormality of mind (whether arising from a condition f arrested or retarded development of mind or any inherent causes or induced by disease or injury) as substantially impaired his mental responsibility for his acts or omissions in doing or being a party to the killing. ” The problems begin with semantics and normative questions of degree: what qualifies as ‘abnormality of mind,’ how much is ‘substantially’ and what is ‘mental responsibility’?

Even debates on the questions have offered little assistance. For ‘abnormality of mind’ referred to conditions ‘bordering on insanity’ while excluding the mere outburst of rage or Jealousy’. Such an explanation is obviously of little worth considering that ‘the response of Judges and psychiatrists? [to the section]? Have ranged from the very generous to the very strict’. In fact the courts it seems, have entertained ‘practically any ground where it was thought morally inappropriate to convict the defendant of murder’.

For example, psychopaths, reactive depressives , alcoholics and those in ‘disassociated states’ or suffering from ‘irresistible impulses’ have all been brought within the protective scope of the section. Lord Parker in Byrne, also attempting to clarify the section’s ambit, said that it dealt tit ‘partial insanity or being on the border line of insanity’. He went on to add that ‘Inability to exercise will-power to control physical acts? Is? Sufficient to entitle the accused to the benefit of this section; difficulty in controlling his acts? May be’.

Confusions are evident here for, as Smith and Hogan note: ‘A man whose impulse is irresistible bears no moral responsibility for his act, for he has no choice; a man whose impulse is much more difficult to resist than that of an ordinary man bears a diminished degree of moral responsibility for his act’ It would appear then, that the roomer should be acquitted as insane rather than have his punishment mitigated. However, if the inability to control his acts is not caused by a ‘defect of reason’ or ‘disease of the mind’ then the defendant has no defense in insanity.

In this respect therefore, the defense of diminished responsibility appears to be patching up the deficiencies of Management; acting as ‘a device for circumventing the embarrassments that flow from a mandatory sentence,’ or the stigma attached to a finding of insanity, by allowing Judges to “follow in a common sense way their sense of fairness. ” Grew, writing in 1988 comments on the section. He suggests that the section is not to be seen as a definitional aid rather it is ‘to be seen as legitimizing an expression of the decision-maker’s personal sense of the proper boundaries between murder and manslaughter’.

The result of the lax and open wording has allowed the defense of diminished responsibility to be used almost as a catch-all excuse, spanning, and adding to, the defenses of insane and non-insane automatism. It has been able to accommodate states of mind and circumstance that would be insufficient for either automatism or insanity whilst at the same time Justifying this accommodation by retire of the increased severity of a murder charge. To some this position is considered entirely unacceptable and contrary to the theories of blame and responsibility discussed hereto.

Sparks for example, comments ‘to say that we are less willing to blame? A man if he does something wrong, surely does not mean: we are willing to blame him less, if he does something wrong. ‘ It would seem however, that due to the inadequacies of Management and the acceptance that some states of mind falling short of insanity should be considered mitigation, the courts had little hospice but to develop the defense of diminished responsibility in this way.

From the issues discussed in this essay it is clear that whilst, in theory, the three defenses of Insanity, Automatism and Diminished Responsibility, do indeed exhibit due to two factors: First, it must be accepted that ‘there is no sharp dividing line between sanity and insanity, but that the two extremes? Shade into one another by imperceptible gradations. ‘ This proposition leads us to conclude that first, the problem is one of definition. Second, the courts are aware that ‘pleading a blackout is one of the first fuses of a guilty conscience and is a popular excuse’.

Therefore, they have tended to view the problem of involuntariness ‘with great circumspection and have adopted a restrictive approach as to when there should be a complete exemption from liability’. In order to balance this definitional problem with the requirement of certainty, whilst ensuring that only the deserving are completely acquitted, the law has had no alternative but to define distinct parameters. It is these parameters which have both caused the fudging of the two automatism defenses and necessitated the creation of a diminished responsibility defense.